Terence Edward "Terry" Horgan (born October 13, 1948) is an American philosopher and a professor at the University of Arizona in Tucson. His areas of expertise include philosophy of mind and metaethics.
Horgan obtained his bachelor's degree in philosophy in 1970 from Stanford University. In 1974, he completed his Ph.D. at the University of Michigan under the supervision of Jaegwon Kim, with his dissertation titled "Microreduction and the Mind-Body Problem." After holding professorships in Illinois, Michigan, and Memphis, Horgan has been a professor in Tucson, Arizona since 2002.
Together with George Graham and Tienson, Horgan developed PIT in a moderate, derivativist direction: many non-phenomenal intentional states (for example, standing beliefs) have their content in virtue of suitable functional or other systematic relations to phenomenal intentional states, rather than being phenomenal themselves.Graham, George; Horgan, Terence E.; Tienson, John L. (2007), "Consciousness and intentionality," in M. Velmans & S. Schneider (eds.), pp. 468–484. They further defended internalism and a corresponding account of narrow content via "brain-in-a-vat" scenarios, arguing that phenomenal consciousness provides the best basis for narrow intentional content even if reference and truth-conditions involve external relations.Horgan, Terence E.; Tienson, John L.; Graham, George (2004), "Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat," in R. Schantz (ed.), pp. 297–318.
Horgan has also linked PIT to issues of content determinacy, contending (with Graham) that purely physical, functional, or informational facts underdetermine the specific contents we represent (e.g., RABBIT vs. UNDETACHED-RABBIT-PARTS), and that appeal to phenomenal character helps explain how content is fixed.Horgan, Terence; Graham, George (2012), "Phenomenal Intentionality and Content Determinacy," in R. Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning, Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 321–344. In parallel, he has been a prominent defender of cognitive phenomenology: he connects agentive phenomenology to thought phenomenology,Horgan, Terence (2011a), "From Agentive Phenomenology to Cognitive Phenomenology: A Guide for the Perplexed," in T. Bayne & M. Montague (eds.), pp. 57–78. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199579938.003.0003. argues for the evidential role of perceptual experience,Horgan, Terence (2011b), "Phenomenal intentionality and the evidential role of perceptual experience: comments on Jack Lyons, Perception and Basic Beliefs," Philosophical Studies 153(3): 447–455. and maintains that original (non-derived) intentionality is phenomenal intentionality.Horgan, Terence (2013), "Original Intentionality is Phenomenal Intentionality," The Monist 96(2): 232–251.
Across these contributions, Horgan (often with Tienson and Graham) has used a range of phenomenological devices—contrast cases, spontaneous-thought examples, and agency-involving experiences—to argue that much of a thinker's web of belief and desire is structured by, or derives from, phenomenal character.Horgan, Terence E.; Tienson, John L. (2002), "The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality," in D. J. Chalmers (ed.), pp. 520–533.Graham, George; Horgan, Terence E.; Tienson, John L. (2007), "Consciousness and intentionality," in M. Velmans & S. Schneider (eds.), pp. 468–484.
To motivate both premises, Horgan, Tienson, and Graham adapt brain-in-a-vat scenarios: a physical duplicate of a subject's brain, sustained and stimulated so as to match the subject's internal states, would (they contend) share the subject's phenomenology; because phenomenal character fixes phenomenal intentional content, many of the duplicate's intentional contents would match the original's too. This is intended to show both the narrowness of phenomenology and the reality of phenomenally determined (hence narrow) content.
Although perceptual experience is the most immediate case, Horgan and collaborators extend the program beyond perception, arguing for distinctive phenomenologies of agency and of propositional attitudes (belief, desire), and for the thesis that all intentionality is either identical with, or derived from, phenomenal intentionality—thereby grounding a broad class of narrow contents for thought as well.
On the theoretical side, Horgan and Tienson suggest affinities between their approach and two-dimensional modal semantics for characterizing content, while related work with Uriah Kriegel emphasizes a broadly descriptive connection between phenomenal intentionality and reference.Kriegel, Uriah; Horgan, Terry (forthcoming). "The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program". In T. Horgan; U. Kriegel (eds.), Phenomenal Intentionality: New Essays. Oxford University Press.
In Austere Realism: Contextual Semantics Meets Minimal Ontology (2008), Horgan and Potrč defended a version called blobjectivism: the view that only one concrete particular exists—the entire cosmos ("the blobject"). Thus, Horgan and Potrč's view is a form of "Existence Monism". This entity has enormous spatiotemporal variability but no proper parts. Truth, on their account, is a matter of indirect correspondence rather than mirroring discrete objects. This view has been discussed in metametaphysical debates.
Multiple realizability might well begin at home. For all we now know (and I emphasize that we really do not now know), the intentional mental states we attribute to one another might turn out to be radically multiply realizable at the neurobiological level of description, even in humans; indeed, even in individual humans; indeed, even in an individual human given the structure of his central nervous system at a single moment of his life. (p. 308; author's emphases)
In an essay from 2002, Horgan describes his ambivalent stance towards physicalism as follows: "I remain deeply attracted to materialism in philosophy of mind; I would like to believe that the mental is supervenience on the physical. But the whole hard problem looks very hard indeed, and I see no prospects currently in sight for dealing with it satisfactorily. … Much as I would like to be a materialist, at present I do not know what an adequate materialist theory of mind would look like."
Horgan's approach to supervenience of moral truths on natural truths, relying on "superdupervenience", has been influential.
In subsequent work, Horgan and Timmons defended cognitivist expressivism (also called nondescriptivist cognitivism). This hybrid theory holds that moral judgments are cognitive states (beliefs) but not descriptive representations of stance-independent facts. Rather, they express evaluative attitudes while still being truth-apt under minimalist semantics. This approach explains the objectivity-like feel of moral discourse without positing robust moral facts.
Together with David Henderson, Horgan has proposed an epistemology called "transglobal reliabilism", which proposes that a belief is justified only if the process that produced it is robustly reliable across a broad set of worlds that are experientially like ours (so it would still work under many variations). This view has been criticized for illegitimately assuming that there are more truth-friendly such worlds than deceptive ones, as well as for proposing an unnecessary requirement for justification. Henderson and Horgan have also proposed a modified version, called "transglobal evidentialism-reliabilism", together with Matjaž Potrč.
The indirect-correspondence component is tied to Horgan and Potrč's "contextual semantics" and their austere realism, which seeks a minimal ontology while preserving the abundant truth of ordinary and scientific discourse. On this picture, many everyday claims can be literally true even if the ontology denies the corresponding entities as fundamental, because their truth is a matter of mediated correspondence given ordinary semantic standards.
Horgan and Barnard describe their position as a form of correspondence pluralism: truth always consists in correspondence, but there are different forms of correspondence across domains. They argue that this preserves a robust, unified notion of truth while allowing variation in how truth is realized (for example, via indirect semantic standards in some areas). Secondary overviews classify Horgan's view alongside pluralist theories that maintain correspondence while allowing different ways of corresponding; the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy explicitly cites Horgan and collaborators in presenting this family of positions.
Reception and discussion emphasize both the robustness and the indirect character of Horgan's correspondence account. Michael P. Lynch analyzes Horgan's "contextual semantics" and labels the overall view "Indirect Correspondence Metaphysical Realism," highlighting its commitment to realism combined with mediated standards for truth. A review of Truth and Pluralism: Current Debates likewise characterizes Barnard & Horgan's contribution as defending a view on which truth is always correspondence but "rarely" direct.
|
|